Tuesday, 31 December 2019

Misconstruing Distractive And Dismissive Clarification (Elaboration) As Addition (Extension)


Martin & Rose (2007: 134):
And there are other common items that are used to add a ‘sidetrack’ to the flow of discourse — anyway, anyhow, incidentally, by the way. Here’s a couple of examples from an anecdote about language teaching and language knowledge:
A teacher was confused about which of affect and effect was the noun or verb (it's affect verb, effect noun by the way, except for one formal meaning of effect 'succeed in causing to happen'), or was perhaps unable to recognise the noun or verb in the sentence he was policing. He marked the student wrong, suggesting affect for effect or vice versa (I can't recall which). Anyhow, as it turned out, the student had been right; the teacher got it wrong. (Martin (2000), Grammar meets Genre).

Blogger Comments:

Here Martin & Rose misconstrue two distinct subclasses of elaboration — dismissive (anyway) and distractive (incidentally, by the way) clarification — as one subclass of extension (addition), and rebrand Halliday's textual grammatical system (cohesive conjunction) as Martin's logical discourse semantic system. Halliday & Matthiessen (2014: 613):

Sunday, 29 December 2019

Misconstruing Continuity As Additive Conjunction


Martin & Rose (2007: 134):
There is also a set of conjunctions that are commonly used in spoken discourse to add new stages to what is being said now, well, alright, okay. Here is an example from Chapter 7:
Luke: You know I missed you two fuckers.
Llewelyn: Sorry I can't say the same Luke.
Zuko: Yeah me too.
Luke: Well fuck you, man.

Blogger Comments:

Here Martin & Rose mistake continuatives for conjunctions, and mistake the system of continuity for the system of additive conjunction.  In additive conjunction, a conjunction serves to mark a cohesive relation of addition — X and Y — between portions of text. In the system of continuity, on the other hand, a continuative cohesively marks a move in dialogue. Halliday & Matthiessen (2014: 107):
A continuative is one of a small set of words that signal a move in the discourse: a response, in dialogue, or a new move to the next point if the same speaker is continuing. The usual continuatives are yes no well oh now. See Halliday & Hasan (1976: Chapter 5).

Friday, 27 December 2019

Misunderstanding Internal Conjunction


Martin & Rose (2007: 133):
The roles of internal conjunction in logically organising discourse have become particularly elaborated in the written mode, building on older spoken ways of meaning. For this reason, internal conjunction includes the same four logical types as we have seen for external conjunctions. Furthermore many of the items that express internal relations are the same as external conjunctions, such as also, thus, but other internal conjunctions are quite different. The basic options are outlined in Table 4.5.

Blogger Comments:

[1] To be clear, in SFL Theory, internal conjunction is not concerned with logically organising discourse. Instead, conjunction, whether internal or external, is a textual system of the lexicogrammar, through which cohesive relations are established between portions of text. This is distinct from the logical system of clause complexing, through which structural relations are established between clause in clause complexes.

The distinction between external and internal conjunction is the distinction between linking representations of experience and linking interpersonal exchanges.  Halliday & Matthiessen (2014: 611):
Relations between representations of segments of experience are called external relations, and conjunctions marking such relations are called external conjunctions. … Relations linking text segments in their interpersonal guise are called internal relations – internal to the text as a speech event, and conjunctions marking such relations are called internal conjunctions.

[2] To be clear, Table 4.5 foreshadows some of the misunderstandings to appear in this discussion. For example:
  • the conjunctive Adjunct for instance marks exemplifying apposition (a subclass of elaboration), not comparison (a subclass of enhancement);
  • the conjunctive Adjunct on the other hand marks adversative addition (a subclass of extension), not comparison (a subclass of enhancement); and
  • the speech-functional comment Adjunct admittedly functions interpersonally, not logically (or textually); see Halliday & Matthiessen (2014: 191).

Tuesday, 24 December 2019

The Full System For External Conjunction

Martin & Rose (2007: 132-3):
The full system for external conjunction is displayed in Table 4.4.
 

Blogger Comments:

[1] Trivially, this is not a system, but a hyponymic taxonomy presented as a table.

[2] As previously demonstrated, the authors' system of external conjunction is a confusion of two distinct grammatical systems, clause complexing (logical metafunction) and cohesive conjunction (textual metafunction) rebranded as a discourse semantic system of the logical metafunction.

Because the original intellectual source of this model is the system of cohesive conjunction in Halliday & Hasan (1976), the logical relations are not organised into the three main subclasses of expansion (elaboration, extension and enhancement), and all subclasses of elaboration and projection are entirely absent from the author's model.  This latter fact is a particularly serious deficiency, since, not only does the model fail to account for the semantics of elaboration and projection, but it disables any attempt to account for grammatical metaphor in which elaboration and projection are featured.

Moreover, as previously demonstrated, Martin & Rose misunderstand each of the seven types of conjunction — see the previous 20 posts — and this has the effect of differentiating their rebranded model from its intellectual source, thereby creating the false impression of original thought.

Sunday, 22 December 2019

Summary Of The Problems With The System Of External Consequence


Martin & Rose (2007: 132):
Options for external consequence, including expectant and concessive cause means, purpose and condition, are shown in Figure 4.4.

Blogger Comments:

[1] As previously demonstrated, in terms of SFL Theory, the authors' system of external consequence comprises a subclass of manner (means), two subclasses of cause (reason and purpose) and condition, all misunderstood, to varying degrees, and rebranded as discourse semantics (instead of grammar). Cf Halliday & Matthiessen (2014: 477-8):

[2] As previously demonstrated, the oppositions 'expectant' vs 'concessive' and 'desire' vs 'fear' derive from misunderstandings of the logical relations involved.  See the previous posts:

[3] To be clear, even in its own terms, this is a poorly conceived network, since it features the same system (expectant vs concessive) four times, instead of once with four disjunctive ('or') entry conditions.

Friday, 20 December 2019

Confusing Condition With Cause

Martin & Rose (2007: 131-2):
Other conjunctions that realise condition include if ..thenprovided thatso long as:
If my life, that of my children and my parents was strangled,
then I would have done the same. 
I would have done the same
provided that there was no risk to my relaxed and comfortable way of life.
These are all conditions under which an event may happen. On the other hand, unless introduces conditions that close off the possibility of an event happening:
... the application should be dealt with in a public hearing
unless such a hearing was likely to lead to a miscarriage of justice
With concessive condition, an effect won’t occur even if a condition is met:
I would not have done the same
even if I had known the truth

Blogger Comments:

[1] To be clear, the primary clauses ('consequents') of conditional clause complexes are not limited to "events that happen", as demonstrated by:
  • If it quacks like a duck, then it probably is a duck

[2] To be clear, in SFL Theory, unless marks negative condition: if not P then Q (Halliday & Matthiessen 2014: 477), and the primary clauses of negative conditions are not limited to "events that happen", as demonstrated by:
  • Unless it quacks like a duck, it probably isn't a duck.

[3] To be clear, the meaning of concessive condition is if P then contrary to expectation Q.

[4] To be clear, the use of 'effect' here, along with the notion of events happening (or not) after a condition is met, betrays the authors' misconstrual of condition as a type of cause. 
Conditional statements are not statements of causality. An important distinction is that statements of causality require the antecedent to precede or coincide with the consequent in time, whereas conditional statements do not require this temporal order.

Tuesday, 17 December 2019

Misunderstanding Condition


Martin & Rose (2007: 131):
Condition is the relation between an outcome and the conditions under which it may occur, as we saw in Helena’s story:
I would have done the same
had I been denied everything.
If my life, that of my children and my parents was strangled with legislation.
If I had to watch how white people became dissatisfied with the best and still wanted better and got it.
With condition the relevant modal meaning is probability. Helena considers it likely that she would join the struggle under sufficient conditions; and the more oppressive the conditions, the more likely she would have been to do the same.

Blogger Comments:

[1] To be clear, the secondary clause of a conditional relation need not be an outcome nor an occurrence.  For example, consider the following clause complex:
  • If the next turn-off is to Nimbin, then we're on the right road.
In this instance, we're on the right road is neither an outcome of the next turn-off is to Nimbin nor an occurrence (a material happening).

[2] To be clear, this is demonstrably untrue, as demonstrated by any and all conditional relations that involve other types of modality:
  • If you use the toilet, you must flush it afterwards (obligation)
  • If you're going to the shops, I'd like to come with you (inclination)
  • If Jim says so, David usually agrees (usuality)

[3] To be clear, the probability in Helena's clause complex is expressed in the modal Finite would, not in the conditional relation between the clauses.

[4] To be clear, this is pure supposition on the part of Martin & Rose.

Sunday, 15 December 2019

Misunderstanding Purpose And Confusing It With (± Concessive) Condition


Martin & Rose (2007: 130-1):
Whereas cause obligates an effect to follow, with purpose the relevant modal meaning is inclination. We take an action because we desire an outcome. As with by for expressing means, the hypotactic conjunction to is a common way of expressing purpose:
To make an informed recommendation,
the RRC committee will use the following two information instruments.
Other conjunctions that realise purpose include so that, in case:
The RRC committee will use the following two information instruments
so that it can make an informed recommendation,
These purpose conjunctions (in order) to, so as, indicate that the outcome is desired. But there is another kind of purpose where the outcome is feared — using lest or for fear of:
the RRC committee will use the following two information instruments
lest it make an uninformed recommendation.
With concessive desire, an action is performed without the effect occurring:
The RRC committee used two information instruments,
without being able to make an informed recommendation. 
The RRC committee used two information instruments,
even so they could not make an informed recommendation.
As fear is already a negative option, there is no concessive alternative.


Blogger Comments:

[1] To be clear, here Martin & Rose misconstrue the clause complexing relation of purpose:
  • because intention Q so action P
as the desire for, or fear of, the result ("outcome", 'effect") of a cause.


[2] To be clear, in case can mark a relation of cause: reason or condition, but not purpose. Cf
  • He trained hard in order to get into the team (purpose)
  • He trained hard in case he got into the team (condition)

[3] To be clear, these are not instances of purpose, but of concessive condition:
  • if P then contrary to expectation Q
  • if The RRC committee used two information instruments then contrary to expectation they could not make an informed recommendation

Friday, 13 December 2019

Misunderstanding Concessive Condition As Concessive Means

Martin & Rose (2007: 130):
With concessive means, one event is unable to happen, in spite of enough having been done to enable it:
Even by confessing
he didn't get amnesty 
National unity and reconciliation may still not be promoted
even by establishing as complete a picture as possible of the causes, nature and extent of the gross violations of human rights.
And but can also be used for concessive means:
He confessed
but he didn't get amnesty.

Blogger Comments:

[1] To be clear, in SFL Theory, the logico-semantic relation obtaining in all three examples is that of concessive condition (if P then contrary to expectation Q).  

In the first two clause complexes, the dependent clause is non-finite, and even by realises the same meaning as despite. The concessive condition relation can be made more explicit by substituting agnate finite clauses:
  • Even though he confessed, he didn't get amnesty.
  • National unity and reconciliation may still not be promoted even though the Commission establishes as complete a picture as possible of the causes, nature and extent of the gross violations of human rights.
That is:
  • if he confessed then contrary to expectation he didn't get amnesty
  • if the Commission establishes as complete a picture as possible of the causes, nature and extent of the gross violations of human rights then contrary to expectation National unity and reconciliation may still not be promoted.
In the above cases, the authors' error derives from taking the preposition by (the view from below) as criterial instead of the meaning being realised (the view from above).

The final clause is the paratactic agnate of the first clause complex, and so is again:
  • if he confessed then contrary to expectation he didn't get amnesty

[2] To be clear, the logical relation between clauses is distinct from the interpersonal notion of ability.  Examples where ability is a feature of the relevant clause are:
  • Even by confessing he wasn't able to get amnesty, and
  • He confessed but wasn't able to get amnesty.

Tuesday, 10 December 2019

Confusing Ideational 'Means' With Interpersonal 'Ability' And With Ideational 'Cause'


Martin & Rose (2007: 129-30):
While causes explain why an effect happens, the relation of means explains how something happens, typically with by:
He expected to get amnesty
by confessing. 
The objectives of the Commission shall be to promote national unity and reconciliation
by establishing as complete a picture as possible of the causes, nature and extent of the gross violations of human rights.
Here the Commission intends to use establishing as complete a picture as possible as the means to promote national unity and reconciliationWhereas cause obligates an effect to follow, the relevant meaning here is ability. Tutu’s argument is that by establishing a complete picture, the Commission will be able to promote unity and reconciliation.
The hypotactic conjunction by is perhaps the most common way we express means. Other conjunctions of means include thus, by this means:
He expected amnesty.
Thus he confessed. 
As complete a picture as possible of the causes, nature and extent of the gross violations of human rights will be established.
By this means the Commission will promote national unity and reconciliation.


Blogger Comments:

[1] To be clear, in SFL Theory, along with 'comparison', 'means' is a subtype of manner. As a logico-semantic relation its meaning is N is via/ by means of M.

[2] To be clear, unknown to Martin & Rose, the logical relation in this instance obtains not between ranking clauses, but between two rank-shifted clauses in a complex serving as clause participant:

The objectives of the Commission
shall be
[[[ to promote national unity and reconciliation || by establishing as complete a picture as possible of the causes, nature and extent of the gross violations of human rights ]]]
Identified Value
Process: relational
Identifier Token

The clause encodes the objectives of the Commission by reference to promoting national unity and reconciliation through the stated means.

[3] To be clear, this again confuses ideational meaning (cause and means) with interpersonal meaning (obligation and ability). Obligating someone to obey the law doesn't cause them to obey the law, as the law courts demonstrate.  Having the ability to play chess is distinct from the means of doing so, as those without chess sets demonstrate.

In this instance, on the one hand, Tutu isn't making an argument; he is setting out the objectives of the Commission. On the other hand, he isn't making claims about its ability; he is identifying its objectives and the means of achieving them (see [2]).

[4] To be clear, the cohesive relation here is cause (because P so result Q):
  • because he expected amnesty so result he confessed.

In this instance, thus has the meaning of 'therefore' and signals a causal relation, rather than the meaning of 'in this way' that would signal a relation of means.

Sunday, 8 December 2019

Confusing Concessive 'But' With Adversative 'But' And Using Ambiguous 'However' To Disambiguate The Two

Martin & Rose (2007: 129):
But the most common realisation of concessive cause is but:
He tried to hide his wild consuming fear,
but I saw it 
I can't handle the man anymore!
But I can't get out
However but can also realise comparison:difference, which can be confusing. We can test whether the relation is concession by trying to substitute but with hypotactic or concessive conjunctions that we know realise consequential meanings, such as although however:
Although he tried to hide his wild consuming fear,
I saw it. 
I can't handle the man anymore!
However I can't get out.
If we substitute conjunctions that realise contrast, they don’t make as much sense (*I can’t handle the man anymore! In contrast I can’t get out. *Whereas he tried to hide his wild consuming fear, I saw it).


Blogger Comments:

[1] To be clear, in SFL Theory, the relation in this instance is concessive condition, not concessive cause.  Its meaning is if P then contrary to expectation Q:
  • if he tried to hide his wild consuming fear then contrary to expectation I saw it
That is, Martin & Rose have misunderstood Halliday's concessive condition as concessive cause, and rebranded their misunderstanding of Halliday's grammatical system of clause complexing as Martin's discourse semantic system of conjunction.

[2] To be clear, in SFL Theory, the relation in this instance is adversative addition, not concessive cause. Its meaning is X and conversely Y:
  • I can’t handle the man anymore and conversely I can’t get out
Compare a concessive misinterpretation:
  • * if I can’t handle the man anymore then contrary to expectation I can’t get out
That is, Martin & Rose have misunderstood Halliday's adversative addition as concessive cause, and rebranded their misunderstanding of Halliday's textual grammatical system of cohesive conjunction as Martin's logical discourse semantic system of conjunction.

[3] As previously demonstrated, Martin & Rose misunderstand Halliday's adversative addition (extension) as a type of comparison (enhancement), variously labelled as different/difference or contrast.

[4] To be clear, the conjunctive Adjunct however, like but, can mark either relation, and so is no guide to disambiguation.  Moreover, in this example, it marks adversative addition ("comparison: difference/contrast"), not concessive condition ("concessive cause") — the opposite of the authors' claim.

[5] To be clear, this is the opposite of what is true.  The relation here is adversative addition (see [2]), which can be rendered cohesively as:
  • I can’t handle the man anymore! On the other hand, I can’t get out.

Friday, 6 December 2019

Misconstruing Concessive Condition As Concessive Cause

Martin & Rose (2007: 128):
In the introduction to this chapter we saw that ordinary conjunctions such as then can signal counterexpectancy in certain contexts. But for consequential conjunctions this is a regular option, so that specific sets of conjunctions realise each type of counterexpectant consequence. These are known as concessive conjunctions. … Concessive cause is realised by although, even though, even if, but, however.
For example Helena’s marriage failed all because she married for the wrong reasons, but it could have failed even though she married for the right reasons:
An extremely short marriage to someone else failed
even though I married for the right reasons.
Helena’s first love was popular with the Afrikaners even if he was an Englishman; in a more tolerant South Africa he might have been popular because he was an Englishman:
Because he was an Englishman,
he was popular with all the 'Boer' Afrikaners.


Blogger Comments:

[1] To be clear, this is the relation of concessive condition (Halliday & Matthiessen 2014: 478) in the grammatical system of clause complexing, misunderstood as concessive cause, and rebranded as discourse semantics.

The meaning of cause (reason) is
  • 'because P so result Q', 
whereas the meaning of concessive condition is
  • 'if P then contrary to expectation Q'.
Conditional statements are not statements of causality. An important distinction is that statements of causality require the antecedent to precede or coincide with the consequent in time, whereas conditional statements do not require this temporal order.

[2] To be clear, the meaning of An extremely short marriage to someone else failed all because I married for the wrong reasons is
  • because I married for the wrong reasons so an extremely short marriage to someone else failed
whereas the meaning of An extremely short marriage to someone else failed even though I married for the right reasons is
  • if I married for the right reasons then contrary to expectation an extremely short marriage to someone else failed.

[3] To be clear, liking someone because of their nationality or ethnic identity is not tolerance, but racial discrimination. Cf Because he was an Aryan, he was popular with the National Socialist Germans; Because she was not Aryan, she was not popular with the National Socialist Germans.

Tuesday, 3 December 2019

Confusing Metafunctions And Rebranding Halliday's Grammar As Martin's Discourse Semantics

Martin & Rose (2007: 128):
Because functions in hypotactic relations; the corresponding paratactic conjunction is so, and cohesive conjunctions include therefore, consequently:
I married to forget,
so my first marriage failed. 
I married to forget.
Consequently my first marriage failed.

Blogger Comments:

To be clear, these are simply grammatical relations — originally devised by Halliday (± Hasan) — that are rebranded here as Martin's logical discourse semantic relations (after Martin 1992).

In SFL Theory, hypotactic and paratactic relations of cause obtain structurally been clauses in a clause nexus, and realise a feature of the logical system of clause complexing.

The above cohesive relation of cause, on the other hand, obtains non-structurally between clause simplexes, and realises a feature of the textual system of cohesive conjunction.

Sunday, 1 December 2019

Confusing Ideational 'Cause' With Interpersonal 'Modulation'

Martin & Rose (2007: 128):
When Helena’s first marriage failed, she explained why it failed, using all because:
An extremely short marriage to someone else failed
all because I married to forget.
The conjunction because means that one event obligates another to happen, as cause and effect. By saying all because, Helena makes this obligatory relation even stronger, i.e. there was only one reason - I married to forget. In other words, cause modulates the relations between one event and the next, and like other such modal meanings (described in Chapter 2 , section 2 .2 ) it is gradable; for example, she could also have weakened the causal relation with partly because. This is an important principle, particularly in science writing, where the strength of causal relations is carefully evaluated.

Blogger Comments:

[1] To be clear, Here Martin & Rose confuse metafunctions: ideational causation with interpersonal modality (modulation: obligation).  The type of cause here involves the logical relation 'because P, so result Q'. Obligation, on the other hand, is the scale between 'do!' and 'don't!': graded from 'required' to 'supposed' to 'allowed'.

[2] This misunderstands cause. To be clear, cause is not gradable: either X is construed as a cause of Y, or it isn't. The variable here is not the relative strength of a causal relation, but whether a result has a single cause (all because) or multiple causes (partly because).

Friday, 29 November 2019

The Four General Types Of External Consequence

Martin & Rose (2007: 127):
There are four general types of external consequence: cause, means, condition, purpose. Some basic options are shown in Table 4.3.

Blogger Comments:

To be clear, this characterisation of the authors' discourse semantic system of external consequence is a rebranding of Halliday's grammatical system of clause complexing that confuses a subtype of manner (means) with 3 subtypes of causal-conditional relations (cause, purpose and condition).  Cf Halliday & Matthiessen (2014: 477):

Tuesday, 26 November 2019

The System Of External Time

Martin & Rose (2007: 127):
So options for external time include successive: sometime or immediate and simultaneous, set out in Figure 4.3. 

Blogger Comments:

To be clear, the authors' logical discourse semantic system of external time is a simplified confusion of the temporal systems of Halliday's grammatical systems of clause complexing (logical metafunction) and cohesive conjunction (textual metafunction).

Halliday & Matthiessen (2014: 477) provide the following temporal distinctions for clause complexing:

Halliday & Matthiessen (2014: 613) provide the following temporal distinctions for cohesive conjunction:

Sunday, 24 November 2019

External Time: Misconstruing 'Simultaneous' As 'Successive'


Martin & Rose (2007: 126-7):
This kind of time relation is successive - events happen one after another. Successive conjunctions used in hypotactic relations include when, after, since, now that:
when I answered the questions
I was told that I was lying
Other successive conjunctions indicate that an event happens immediately before or after, including once, as soon as… :
as soon as I answered
I was slapped again
… Cohesive successive conjunctions include subsequently, previously, at once:
I answered the questions.
Subsequently I was told that I was lying. 
He said he was going on a 'trip'.
Previously it had been a beautiful relationship. 
I started fighting back.
At once four, maybe five policemen viciously knocked me down.
… Cohesive simultaneous conjunctions include meanwhile, simultaneously:
cohesive
The old White South Africa slept peacefully.
Meanwhile 'those at the top' were again targeting the next 'permanent removal from society'.


Blogger Comments:

[1] To be clear, when, once, as soon as signal 'same' time, not 'different' time.  This can be demonstrated by substituting them with at the time:
at the time I answered the questions
I was told I was lying
at the time I answered
I was slapped again 
 Different time is commonly signalled by before or after:
before/after I answered the questions
I was told I was lying
before/after I answered
I was slapped again
[2] To be clear, cohesion is a textual system on the stratum of lexicicogrammar.  Its details were painstakingly elaborated by Halliday & Hasan (1976). Here Martin & Rose rebrand it as Martin's logical system on Martin's stratum of discourse semantics (following Martin 1992).

By the same token, the earlier "non-cohesive" examples are instances of clause complexing, a logical system on the stratum of lexicogrammar.  Its details were painstakingly elaborated by Halliday (1985). Here Martin & Rose rebrand it as Martin's logical system on Martin's stratum of discourse semantics (following Martin 1992).

Friday, 22 November 2019

Problems With The System Of External Comparison

Martin & Rose (2007: 125):
In sum, options for external comparison include similarity or difference: opposite, replacing or excepting, set out in Figure 4.2.

Blogger Comments:

To be clear, the authors' system of comparison misconstrues 3 subtypes of extension as 3 subtypes of comparison (enhancement) and rebrands these grammatical features as discourse semantic. Specifically:
  1. adversative addition is misconstrued as comparison and rebranded as different: opposite;
  2. replacive variation is misconstrued as comparison and rebranded as different: replacing;
  3. subtractive variation is misconstrued as comparison and rebranded as different: excepting.

Cf. Halliday & Matthiessen (2014: 471):

Again, the serious theoretical disadvantage of misunderstanding these expansion relations and rebranding them as discourse semantics is that it creates an incongruent relation between grammar and discourse semantics even in the absence of grammatical metaphor.

Tuesday, 19 November 2019

Misconstruing A Substitute As A Continuative

Martin & Rose (2007: 125):
Of course the flipside of contrast is similarity, using like, as if:
The criminal and civil liability of the perpetrator are expunged as if the offence had never happened.
Here Tutu uses as if to suggest that liability expunged is in some way similar to the offence never happened. A cohesive conjunction that can express external similarity is similarly:
Helena's first love worked in a top security structure. Similarly her second love worked for the special forces.
Similarity can also be expressed by the continuative so, with Subject-Finite inversion:
I was torn to pieces. So was he.

Blogger Comments:

[1] To be clear, similarity is the "flipside" of difference.  In SFL Theory, the logical meaning of comparison is 'N is like M', and the relation is marked by and + similarly; (and) so, thus, as, as if, like, the way, like (Halliday & Matthiessen 2014: 477).

[2] To be clear, the logical meaning of this clause complex is: The criminal and civil liability of the perpetrator are expunged is like the offence had never happened.

[3] To be clear, in SFL theory, cohesive conjunction is a grammatical system of the textual metafunction. Here Martin & Rose blend it with the logical grammatical system of clause complexing, and rebrand the confusion as logical discourse semantics.

[4] To be clear, in this instance, the word so is a substitution for the Residue of the clause — not a continuative.  In SFL Theory, genuine continuatives are items such as well, oh, oh no etc.

Sunday, 17 November 2019

Misconstruing Replacive And Subtractive Variation As Comparison

Martin & Rose (2007: 124-5):
As with lexical contrasts, there is more than one kind of logical difference. First, one meaning can be replaced by another using instead of, in place of, rather than. These are all used in hypotactic relations:
Instead of resting at night, he would wander from window to window.
A third kind of difference is to make an exception, using except that, other than, apart from, which are again hypotactic:
He wanted to rest at night except that he kept having nightmares. 
He used to rest at night other than when he had nightmares.
Conjunctions like instead and rather can also be used as cohesive:
He should have slept at night. Instead he would wander from window to window.

Blogger Comments:

[1] To be clear, here Martin & Rose misunderstand a subtype of extension, replacive variation, as 'replaced', a subtype of comparison (enhancement), and rebrand their misunderstanding of the grammatical system as discourse semantics. In SFL theory, replacive variation is the term for the logical meaning 'not X but Y', and is marked by such items as but not; not ... but, instead of, rather than (Halliday & Matthiessen 2014: 471).

[2] To be clear, here Martin & Rose misunderstand a subtype of extension, subtractive variation, as  'exception', a subtype of comparison (enhancement), and rebrand their misunderstanding of the grammatical system as discourse semantics. In SFL theory, subtractive variation is the term for the logical meaning 'X but not all X', and is marked by such items as only, but, except, except that, but (for the fact) that except for, other than (Halliday & Matthiessen 2014: 471).

[3] To be clear, in SFL theory, cohesive conjunction is a grammatical system of the textual metafunction.  Here Martin & Rose blend it with the logical grammatical system of clause complexing, and rebrand the confusion as logical discourse semantics.

Friday, 15 November 2019

Misconstruing Replacive Variation And Adversative Addition As Comparison


Martin & Rose (2007: 124):
The basic options for comparison are similarity versus difference. Perhaps the most common kind of comparison is to contrast two clauses as different, using but:
This is not a frivolous question, but a very serious issue.
Here Tutu contrasts two abstract things, a question and an issue. There is a lexical contrast between their qualities - frivolous versus very serious - and this contrast is made explicit with but. The particular type of difference here is opposition: frivolous and serious realise opposite experiential meanings. But is used in paratactic relations, and opposition can also be realised in hypotactic relations with whereas, while:
Whereas this is a simple question, it is a very serious issue.

Blogger Comments:

[1] To be clear, in SFL Theory, the logical meaning of comparison is 'N is like M', and it is marked by items such as and + similarly; (and) so, thus as, as if, like, the way like (Halliday & Matthiessen 2014: 477).  Comparison is a subtype of enhancement.

[2] To be clear, in SFL theory, the logical meaning 'not X but Y' is termed replacive variation, and it is marked by such items as but not; not ... but, instead of, rather than (Halliday & Matthiessen 2014: 471). Replacive variation is a subtype of extension.

Given that Martin & Rose distinguish 'opposite' (i.e. 'adversative' in SFL) from 'replacing' ('instead of'), their analysis of this relation as 'opposite' rather than 'replacing' is even inconsistent with the distinctions of their own model.

[3] To be clear, the relation here obtains between nominal groups, not clauses, which is consistent with the authors' discussion of the elements that are contrasted.

this
is
not a frivolous question but a very serious issue
Carrier
Process: attributive
Attribute
Subject
Finite
Predicator
Complement
Mood
Residue

not
a frivolous question
but
a very serious issue

1

+ 2


[4] To be clear, in SFL theory, the logical meaning 'X and conversely Y' is termed adversative addition, and it is marked by such items as but, (and) yet while, whereas (Halliday & Matthiessen 2014: 471). Adversative addition is a subtype of extension.

That is, Martin & Rose here misunderstand adversative addition (extension), on the grammatical stratum, as a subtype of comparison (enhancement) and rebrand their misunderstanding as 'opposite', on the discourse semantic stratum.

Tuesday, 12 November 2019

Problems With The System Of External Addition

Martin & Rose (2007: 124):
In sum, options for external addition include adding, subtracting and alternation, set out in Figure 4.1.
 

Blogger Comments:

To be clear, the problems with the authors' rebranding of Halliday's grammatical system of extension as a discourse semantic system of addition can be made explicit by comparing it with the systemic categories it misunderstands; Halliday & Matthiessen (2014: 471):
It can be seen that Figure 4.1 only models 3 of the 6 categories of extension:
  1. additive: positive (rebranded as 'add'),
  2. additive: negative (misunderstood as 'subtract'), and
  3. alternation.
The authors' misunderstanding of negative addition as 'subtract' creates the further logical inconsistency of 'subtract' being construed as a subtype of 'additive'.

It will be seen in a later post that Martin & Rose misconstrue the 3 omitted categories of extension:
  1. addition: adversative,
  2. variation: replacive, and
  3. variation: subtractive
as subtypes of comparison, which in SFL theory, is a subtype of enhancement, not extension.

A further theoretical disadvantage of misunderstanding these expansion relations and rebranding them as discourse semantics is that it creates an incongruent relation between grammar and discourse semantics even in the absence of grammatical metaphor.

Sunday, 10 November 2019

Problems With Examples Of External Addition


Martin & Rose (2007: 122-4):
We have seen that and can function to add clauses together in a paratactic sequence, one after another:
... white people became dissatisfied with the best
and still wanted better
and got it
 
Four, maybe five policemen viciously knocked me down,
and they put me back on the chair
and handcuffed my hands through the chair
… Other conjunctions that realise alternation include if not-then, alternatively:
dependent
If they don't want restorative justice,
then they could choose retribution.
 
cohesive
A witness may be terminally ill.
Alternatively she might be disabled.

Blogger Comments:

To be clear, these are all grammatical relations, rebranded as discourse semantic relations, with no argument supporting the claim that these relations obtain at a higher level of symbolic abstraction.

[1] To be clear, the relation here is not addition (extension), but time (enhancement), since it relates two clauses in a nexus in terms of temporal sequence.  This error demonstrates the folly of taking form as the point of departure for ascribing function.  As Halliday & Matthiessen (2014: 487) point out, the conjunction and can mark not only additive extension ('and also'), but also temporal enhancement ('and then') and causal enhancement ('and so').

[2] To be clear, the relation here is not alternative addition (extension), but condition (enhancement).  If the relation were one of alternation, the clause complex would be agnate to Either they don't want restorative justice or they could choose retribution.  A genuine example of alternation would be If it's not circular then it's elliptical (cf. Either it's circular or it's elliptical).  This again shows the folly of taking form as the point of departure for ascribing function.

[3] To be clear, in SFL theory, the function of the expansion relation here is textual, not logical (as well as being grammatical, not discourse semantic).  The relation here is non-structural, whereas logical relations obtain structurally between rank units in complexes.